Skip to main content
Mathematics LibreTexts

3.5: Even More Direct Proofs- By Cases and By Exhaustion

  • Page ID
    19378
  • \( \newcommand{\vecs}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \) \( \newcommand{\vecd}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash {#1}}} \)\(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)\(\newcommand{\AA}{\unicode[.8,0]{x212B}}\)

    Proof by exhaustion is the least attractive proof method from an aesthetic perspective. An exhaustive proof consists of literally (and exhaustively) checking every element of the universe to see if the given statement is true for it. Usually, of course, this is impossible because the universe of discourse is infinite; but when the universe of discourse is finite, one certainly can’t argue the validity of an exhaustive proof.

    In the last few decades, the introduction of powerful computational assistance for mathematicians has lead to a funny situation. There is a growing list of important results that have been “proved” by exhaustion using a computer. Important examples of this phenomenon are the non-existence of a projective plane of order \(10\) [10] and the only known value of a Ramsey number for hypergraphs [13].

    Proof by cases is subtly different from exhaustive proof – for one thing a valid proof by cases can be used in an infinite universe. In a proof by cases, one has to divide the universe of discourse into a finite number of sets1 and then provide a separate proof for each of the cases. A great many statements about the integers can be proved using the division of integers into even and odd. Another set of cases that is used frequently is the finite number of possible remainders obtained when dividing by an integer \(d\). (Note that even and odd correspond to the remainders \(0\) and \(1\) obtained after division by \(2\).)

    A very famous instance of proof by cases is the computer-assisted proof of the four-color theorem. The four-color theorem is a result known to map makers for quite some time that says that \(4\) colors are always sufficient to color the nations on a map in such a way that countries sharing a boundary are always colored differently. Figure \(3.5.1\) shows one instance of an arrangement of nations that requires at least four different colors, the theorem says that four colors are always enough. It should be noted that real cartographers usually reserve a fifth color for oceans (and other water) and that it is possible to conceive of a map requiring five colors if one allows the nations to be non-contiguous. In \(1977\), Kenneth Appel and Wolfgang Haken proved the four-color theorem by reducing the infinitude of possibilities to \(1,936\) separate cases and analyzing each of these with a computer. The inelegance of a proof by cases is probably proportional to some power of the number of cases, but in any case, this proof is generally considered somewhat inelegant. Ever since the proof was announced there has been an ongoing effort to reduce the number of cases (currently the record is \(633\) cases – still far too many to be checked through without a computer) or to find a proof that does not rely on cases. For a good introductory article on the four-color theorem see [6].

    Screen Shot 2021-08-10 at 8.52.41 AM.png
    Figure \(\PageIndex{1}\): The nations surrounding Luxembourg show that sometimes \(4\) colors are required in cartography. (Copyright; author via source)

    Most exhaustive proofs of statements that aren’t trivial tend to either be (literally) too exhausting or to seem rather contrived. One example of a situation in which an exhaustive proof of some statement exists is when the statement is thought to be universally true but no general proof is known – yet the statement has been checked for a large number of cases. Goldbach’s conjecture is one such statement. Christian Goldbach [4] was a mathematician born in Königsberg Prussia, who, curiously, did not make the conjecture2. which bears his name. In a letter to Leonard Euler, Goldbach conjectured that every odd number greater than \(5\) could be expressed as the sum of three primes (nowadays this is known as the weak Goldbach conjecture). Euler apparently liked the problem and replied to Goldbach stating what is now known as Goldbach’s conjecture: Every even number greater than \(2\) can be expressed as the sum of two primes. This statement has been lying around since \(1742\), and a great many of the world’s best mathematicians have made their attempts at proving it – to no avail! (Well, actually a lot of progress has been made but the result still hasn’t been proved.) It’s easy to verify the Goldbach conjecture for relatively small even numbers, so what has been done is/are proofs by exhaustion of Goldbach’s conjecture restricted to finite universes. As of this writing, the conjecture has been verified to be true of all even numbers less than \(2 × 10^{17}\).

    Whenever an exhaustive proof, or a proof by cases exists for some statement it is generally felt that a direct proof would be more esthetically pleasing. If you are in a situation that doesn’t admit such a direct proof, you should at least seek a proof by cases using the minimum possible number of cases. For example, consider the following theorem and proof.

    Theorem \(\PageIndex{1}\)

    \(∀n ∈ \mathbb{Z} n^2\) is of the form \(4k\) or \(4k + 1\) for some \(k ∈ \mathbb{Z}\).

    Proof

    We will consider the four cases determined by the four possible residues \(\text{mod } 4\).

    case i) If \(n ≡ 0\) \((\text{mod } 4)\) then there is an integer \(m\) such that \(n = 4m\). It follows that \(n^2 = (4m)^2 = 16m^2\) is of the form \(4k\) where \(k\) is \(4m^2\).

    case ii) If \(n ≡ 1\) \((\text{mod } 4)\) then there is an integer \(m\) such that \(n = 4m + 1\). It follows that \(n^2 = (4m + 1)^2 = 16m^2 + 8m + 1\) is of the form \(4k + 1\) where k is \(4m^2 + 2m\).

    case iii) If \(n ≡ 2\) \((\text{mod } 4)\) then there is an integer \(m\) such that \(n = 4m + 2\). It follows that \(n^2 = (4m + 2)^2 = 16m^2 + 16m + 4\) is of the form \(4k\) where \(k\) is \(4m^2 + 4m + 1\).

    case iv) If \(n ≡ 3\) \((\text{mod } 4)\) then there is an integer \(m\) such that \(n = 4m + 3\). It follows that \(n^2 = (4m + 3)^2 = 16m^2 + 24m + 9\) is of the form \(4k + 1\) where \(k\) is \(4m^2 + 6m + 2\).

    Since these four cases exhaust the possibilities and since the desired result holds in each case, our proof is complete.

    Q.E.D.

    While the proof just stated is certainly valid, the argument is inelegant since a smaller number of cases would suffice.

    Practice

    The previous theorem can be proved using just two cases. Do so.

    We’ll close this section by asking you to determine an exhaustive proof where the complexity of the argument is challenging but not too impossible.

    Graph pebbling is an interesting concept originated by the famous combinatorialist Fan Chung. A “graph” (as the term is used here) is a collection of places or locations which are known as “nodes,” some of which are joined by paths or connections which are known as “edges.” Graphs have been studied by mathematicians for about \(400\) years, and many interesting problems can be put in this setting. Graph pebbling is a crude version of a broader problem in resource management – often a resource actually gets used in the process of transporting it. Think of the big tanker trucks that are used to transport gasoline. What do they run on? Well, actually they probably burn diesel — but the point is that in order to move the fuel around we have to consume some of it. Graph pebbling takes this to an extreme: in order to move one pebble we must consume one pebble.

    Imagine that a bunch of pebbles are randomly distributed on the nodes of a graph, and that we are allowed to do graph pebbling moves – we remove two pebbles from some node and place a single pebble on a node that is connected to it. See Figure \(3.5.3\).

    Screen Shot 2021-08-10 at 9.02.32 AM.png
    Figure \(\PageIndex{2}\): In graph pebbling problems a collection of pebbles are distributed on the nodes of a graph. There is no significance to the particular graph that is shown here, or to the arrangement of pebbles – we are just giving an example. (Copyright; author via source)

    For any particular graph, we can ask for its pebbling number, \(ρ\). This is the smallest number so that if ρ pebbles are distributed in any way whatsoever on the nodes of the graph, it will be possible to use pebbling moves so as to get a pebble to any node.

    For example, consider the triangle graph – three nodes which are all mutually connected. The pebbling number of this graph is \(3\). If we start with one pebble on each node we are already done; if there is a node that has two pebbles on it, we can use a pebbling move to reach either of the other two nodes.

    Screen Shot 2021-08-10 at 9.03.11 AM.png
    Figure \(\PageIndex{3}\): A graph pebbling move takes two pebbles off of a node and puts one of them on an adjacent node (the other is discarded). Notice how node \(\text{C}\), which formerly held \(3\) pebbles, now has only \(1\) and that a pebble is now present on node \(\text{D}\) where previously there was none. (Copyright; author via source)
    Practice

    There is a graph \(C_5\) which consists of \(5\) nodes connected in a circular fashion. Determine its pebbling number. Prove your answer exhaustively.

    Hint: the pebbling number must be greater than \(4\) because if one pebble is placed on each of \(4\) nodes the configuration is unmovable (we need to have two pebbles on a node in order to be able to make a pebbling move at all) and so the \(5^{\text{th}}\) node can never be reached.

    Exercises:

    Exercise \(\PageIndex{1}\)

    Prove that if \(n\) is an odd number then \(n^4 (\text{mod } 16) = 1\).

    Exercise \(\PageIndex{2}\)

    Prove that every prime number other than \(2\) and \(3\) has the form \(6q + 1\) or \(6q + 5\) for some integer \(q\).

    Hint

    This problem involves thinking about cases as well as contrapositives.

    Exercise \(\PageIndex{3}\)

    Show that the sum of any three consecutive integers is divisible by \(3\).

    Exercise \(\PageIndex{4}\)

    There is a graph known as \(K_4\) that has \(4\) nodes and there is an edge between every pair of nodes. The pebbling number of \(K_4\) has to be at least \(4\) since it would be possible to put one pebble on each of \(3\) nodes and not be able to reach the remaining node using pebbling moves. Show that the pebbling number of \(K_4\) is actually \(4\).

    Exercise \(\PageIndex{5}\)

    Find the pebbling number of a graph whose nodes are the corners and whose edges are the, uhmm, edges of a cube.

    Exercise \(\PageIndex{6}\)

    A vampire number is a \(2n\) digit number \(v\) that factors as \(v = xy\) where \(x\) and \(y\) are \(n\) digit numbers and the digits of \(v\) are precisely the digits in \(x\) and \(y\) in some order. The numbers \(x\) and \(y\) are known as the “fangs” of \(v\). To eliminate trivial cases, both fangs can’t end with \(0\).

    Show that there are no \(2\)-digit vampire numbers.

    Show that there are seven \(4\)-digit vampire numbers

    Exercise \(\PageIndex{7}\)

    Lagrange’s theorem on representation of integers as sums of squares says that every positive integer can be expressed as the sum of at most \(4\) squares. For example, \(79 = 7^2 + 5^2 + 2^2 + 1^2\). Show (exhaustively) that \(15\) can not be represented using fewer than \(4\) squares.

    Exercise \(\PageIndex{8}\)

    Show that there are exactly \(15\) numbers \(x\) in the range \(1 ≤ x ≤ 100\) that can’t be represented using fewer than \(4\) squares.

    Exercise \(\PageIndex{9}\)

    The trichotomy property of the real numbers simply states that every real number is either positive or negative or zero. Trichotomy can be used to prove many statements by looking at the three cases that it guarantees. Develop a proof (by cases) that the square of any real number is non-negative.

    Exercise \(\PageIndex{10}\)

    Consider the game called “binary determinant tic-tac-toe”3 which is played by two players who alternately fill in the entries of a \(3 × 3\) array. Player One goes first, placing \(1\)’s in the array and player Zero goes second, placing \(0\)’s. Player One’s goal is that the final array have determinant \(1\), and player Zero’s goal is that the determinant be \(0\). The determinant calculations are carried out \(\text{mod } 2\).

    Show that player Zero can always win a game of binary determinant tic-tac-toe by the method of exhaustion.


    This page titled 3.5: Even More Direct Proofs- By Cases and By Exhaustion is shared under a GNU Free Documentation License 1.3 license and was authored, remixed, and/or curated by Joseph Fields.

    • Was this article helpful?