Skip to main content
Mathematics LibreTexts

6.2: Lagrange's Theorem

  • Page ID
    81068
  • \( \newcommand{\vecs}[1]{\overset { \scriptstyle \rightharpoonup} {\mathbf{#1}} } \) \( \newcommand{\vecd}[1]{\overset{-\!-\!\rightharpoonup}{\vphantom{a}\smash {#1}}} \)\(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \(\newcommand{\id}{\mathrm{id}}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\) \( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\range}{\mathrm{range}\,}\) \( \newcommand{\RealPart}{\mathrm{Re}}\) \( \newcommand{\ImaginaryPart}{\mathrm{Im}}\) \( \newcommand{\Argument}{\mathrm{Arg}}\) \( \newcommand{\norm}[1]{\| #1 \|}\) \( \newcommand{\inner}[2]{\langle #1, #2 \rangle}\) \( \newcommand{\Span}{\mathrm{span}}\)\(\newcommand{\AA}{\unicode[.8,0]{x212B}}\)

    Proposition \(6.9\)

    Let \(H\) be a subgroup of \(G\) with \(g \in G\) and define a map \(\phi:H \rightarrow gH\) by \(\phi(h) = gh\text{.}\) The map \(\phi\) is bijective; hence, the number of elements in \(H\) is the same as the number of elements in \(gH\text{.}\)

    Proof

    We first show that the map \(\phi\) is one-to-one. Suppose that \(\phi(h_1) = \phi(h_2)\) for elements \(h_1, h_2 \in H\text{.}\) We must show that \(h_1 = h_2\text{,}\) but \(\phi(h_1) = gh_1\) and \(\phi(h_2) = gh_2\text{.}\) So \(gh_1 = gh_2\text{,}\) and by left cancellation \(h_1= h_2\text{.}\) To show that \(\phi\) is onto is easy. By definition every element of \(gH\) is of the form \(gh\) for some \(h \in H\) and \(\phi(h) = gh\text{.}\)

    Theorem \(6.10\). Lagrange

    Let \(G\) be a finite group and let \(H\) be a subgroup of \(G\text{.}\) Then \(|G|/|H| = [G : H]\) is the number of distinct left cosets of \(H\) in \(G\text{.}\) In particular, the number of elements in \(H\) must divide the number of elements in \(G\text{.}\)

    Proof

    The group \(G\) is partitioned into \([G : H]\) distinct left cosets. Each left coset has \(|H|\) elements; therefore, \(|G| = [G : H] |H|\text{.}\)

    Corollary \(6.11\)

    Suppose that \(G\) is a finite group and \(g \in G\text{.}\) Then the order of \(g\) must divide the number of elements in \(G\text{.}\

    Corollary \(6.12\)

    Let \(|G| = p\) with \(p\) a prime number. Then \(G\) is cyclic and any \(g \in G\) such that \(g \neq e\) is a generator.

    Proof

    Let \(g\) be in \(G\) such that \(g \neq e\text{.}\) Then by Corollary 6.11, the order of \(g\) must divide the order of the group. Since \(|\langle g \rangle| \gt 1\text{,}\) it must be \(p\text{.}\) Hence, \(g\) generates \(G\text{.}\)

    Corollary \(6.12\) suggests that groups of prime order \(p\) must somehow look like \({\mathbb Z}_p\text{.}\)

    Corollary \(6.13\)

    Let \(H\) and \(K\) be subgroups of a finite group \(G\) such that \(G \supset H \supset K\text{.}\) Then

    \[ [G:K] = [G:H][H:K]\text{.} \nonumber \]

    Proof

    Observe that

    \[ [G:K] = \frac{|G|}{|K|} = \frac{|G|}{|H|} \cdot \frac{|H|}{|K|} = [G:H][H:K]\text{.} \nonumber \]

    Remark \(6.14\). The converse of Lagrange's Theorem is false

    The group \(A_4\) has order \(12\text{;}\) however, it can be shown that it does not possess a subgroup of order \(6\text{.}\) According to Lagrange's Theorem, subgroups of a group of order \(12\) can have orders of either \(1\text{,}\) \(2\text{,}\) \(3\text{,}\) \(4\text{,}\) or \(6\text{.}\) However, we are not guaranteed that subgroups of every possible order exist. To prove that \(A_4\) has no subgroup of order \(6\text{,}\) we will assume that it does have such a subgroup \(H\) and show that a contradiction must occur. Since \(A_4\) contains eight \(3\)-cycles, we know that \(H\) must contain a \(3\)-cycle. We will show that if \(H\) contains one \(3\)-cycle, then it must contain more than \(6\) elements.

    Proposition \(6.15\)

    The group \(A_4\) has no subgroup of order \(6\text{.}\)

    Proof

    Since \([A_4 : H] = 2\text{,}\) there are only two cosets of \(H\) in \(A_4\text{.}\) Inasmuch as one of the cosets is \(H\) itself, right and left cosets must coincide; therefore, \(gH = Hg\) or \(g H g^{-1} = H\) for every \(g \in A_4\text{.}\) Since there are eight \(3\)-cycles in \(A_4\text{,}\) at least one \(3\)-cycle must be in \(H\text{.}\) Without loss of generality, assume that \((123)\) is in \(H\text{.}\) Then \((123)^{-1} = (132)\) must also be in \(H\text{.}\) Since \(g h g^{-1} \in H\) for all \(g \in A_4\) and all \(h \in H\) and

    \begin{align*} (124)(123)(124)^{-1} & = (124)(123)(142) = (243)\\ (243)(123)(243)^{-1} & = (243)(123)(234) = (142) \end{align*}

    we can conclude that \(H\) must have at least seven elements

    \[ (1), (123), (132), (243), (243)^{-1} = (234), (142), (142)^{-1} = (124)\text{.} \nonumber \]

    Therefore, \(A_4\) has no subgroup of order \(6\text{.}\)

    In fact, we can say more about when two cycles have the same length.

    Theorem \(6.16\)

    Two cycles \(\tau\) and \(\mu\) in \(S_n\) have the same length if and only if there exists a \(\sigma \in S_n\) such that \(\mu = \sigma \tau \sigma^{-1}\text{.}\)

    Proof

    Suppose that

    \begin{align*} \tau & = (a_1, a_2, \ldots, a_k )\\ \mu & = (b_1, b_2, \ldots, b_k )\text{.} \end{align*}

    Define \(\sigma\) to be the permutation

    \begin{align*} \sigma( a_1 ) & = b_1\\ \sigma( a_2 ) & = b_2\\ & \vdots\\ \sigma( a_k ) & = b_k\text{.} \end{align*}

    Then \(\mu = \sigma \tau \sigma^{-1}\text{.}\)

    Conversely, suppose that \(\tau = (a_1, a_2, \ldots, a_k )\) is a \(k\)-cycle and \(\sigma \in S_n\text{.}\) If \(\sigma( a_i ) = b\) and \(\sigma( a_{(i \bmod k) + 1}) = b'\text{,}\) then \(\mu( b) = b'\text{.}\) Hence,

    \[ \mu = ( \sigma(a_1), \sigma(a_2), \ldots, \sigma(a_k) )\text{.} \nonumber \]

    Since \(\sigma\) is one-to-one and onto, \(\mu\) is a cycle of the same length as \(\tau\text{.}\)


    This page titled 6.2: Lagrange's Theorem is shared under a GNU Free Documentation License 1.3 license and was authored, remixed, and/or curated by Thomas W. Judson (Abstract Algebra: Theory and Applications) via source content that was edited to the style and standards of the LibreTexts platform; a detailed edit history is available upon request.

    • Was this article helpful?