Loading [MathJax]/jax/output/HTML-CSS/jax.js
Skip to main content
Library homepage
 

Text Color

Text Size

 

Margin Size

 

Font Type

Enable Dyslexic Font
Mathematics LibreTexts

2.2: Natural Numbers. Induction

( \newcommand{\kernel}{\mathrm{null}\,}\)

The element 1 was introduced in Axiom 4(b). Since addition is also assumed known, we can use it to define, step by step, the elements

2=1+1,3=2+1,4=3+1, etc.

If this process is continued indefinitely, we obtain what is called the set N of all natural elements in the given field F. In particular, the natural elements of E1 are called natural numbers. Note that

(nN)n+1N

*A more precise approach to natural elements is as follows. A subset S of a field F is said to be inductive iff

(i)1S and (ii)(xS)x+1S

Such subsets certainly exist; e.g., the entire field F is inductive since

1F and (xF)x+1F.

Define N as the intersection of all inductive sets in F.

Theorem 2.2.1

The set N so defined is inductive itself. In fact, it is the "smallest" inductive subset of F (i . e ., contained in any other such subset).

Proof

We have to show that

(i)1N, and (ii)(xN)x+1N.

Now, by definition, the unity 1 is in each inductive set; hence it also belongs to the intersection of such sets, i.e., to N. Thus 1N, as claimed.

Next, take any xN. Then, by our definition of N,x is in each inductive set S; thus, by property (ii) of such sets, also x+1 is in each such S ; hence x+1 is in the intersection of all inductive sets, i.e.,

x+1N

and so N is inductive, indeed.

Finally, by definition, N is the common part of all such sets and hence contained in each.

For applications, Theorem 1 is usually expressed as follows.

Theorem 2.2.1

(first induction law). A proposition P(n) involving a natural n holds for all nN in a field F if

(i) it holds for n=1, i.e., P(1) is true; and (ii) whenever P(n) holds for n=m, it holds for n=m+1, i.e., 

P(m)P(m+1).

Proof

Let S be the set of all those nN for which P(n) is true,

S={nN|P(n)}

We have to show that actually each nN is in S, i.e., NS

First, we show that S is inductive.

Indeed, by assumption (i),P(1) is true; so 1S.

Next, let xS. This means that P(x) is true. By assumption (ii), however, this implies P(x+1), i.e., x+1S. Thus

1S and (xS)x+1S

S is inductive.

Then, by Theorem 1 (second clause), NS, and all is proved.

This theorem is used to prove various properties of N "by induction."

Example 2.2.1

(a) If m,nN, then also m+nN and mnN.

To prove the first property, fix any mN. Let P(n) mean

m+nN(nN)

Then

(i) P(1) is true, for as mN, the definition of N yields m+1N, i.e., P(1).

(ii) P(k)P(k+1) for kN. Indeed,

P(k)m+kN(m+k)+1N m+(k+1)NP(k+1)

Thus, by Theorem 1,P(n) holds for all n; i.e.,

(nN)m+nN

for any mN.

To prove the same for mn, we let P(n) mean

mnN(nN)

and proceed similarly.

(b) If nN, then n1=0 or n1N.

For an inductive proof, let P(n) mean

n1=0 or n1N(nN)

Then proceed as in (a).

(c) In an ordered field, all naturals are 1.

Indeed, let P(n) mean that

n1(nN).

Then

(i) P(1) holds since 1=1
(ii) P(m)P(m+1) for mN, since

P(m)m1(m+1)>1P(m+1)

Thus Theorem 1 yields the result.

(d) In an ordered field, m,nN and m>n implies mnN
For an inductive proof, fix any mN and let P(n) mean

mn0 or mnN(nN).

Use (b).

(e) In an ordered field, m,nN and m<n+1 implies mn
For, by (d),m>n would imply mnN, hence mn1, or mn+1, contrary to m<n+1.

Our next theorem states the so-called well-ordering property of N.

Theorem 2.2.2 (well-ordering of N)

In an ordered field, each nonvoid set AN has a least member (i.e., one that exceeds no other element of A).

Proof

The following is just an outline of a proof:

Given AN, let P(n) be the proposition "Any subset of A containing elements n has a least member" (nN). Use Theorem 1 and Example (e) .

This theorem yields a new form of the induction law.

Theorem 2.2.2 (second induction law)

A proposition P(n) holds for all nN

(i') P(1) holds and
(ii') whenever P(n) holds for all naturals less than some mN, then P(n)
also holds for n=m.

Proof

Assume (i) and (ii). Seeking a contradiction, suppose there are some nN( call them "bad") for which P(n) fails. Then these "bad" naturals form a nonvoid subset of N, call it A.

By Theorem 2,A has a least member m. Thus m is the least natural for which P(n) fails. It follows that all n less than m do satisfy P(n). But then, by our assumption (ii'), P(n) also holds for n=m, which is impossible for, by construction, m is "bad" (it is in A). This contradiction shows that there are no "bad" naturals. Thus all is proved.

Note 1: All the preceding arguments hold also if, in our definition of N and all formulations, the unity 1 is replaced by 0 or by some k(±kN). Then, however, the conclusions must be changed to say that P(n) holds for all integers nk (instead of "n \geq 1 "). We then say that "induction starts with k."

An analogous induction law also applies to definitions of concepts C(n).

A notion C(n) involving a natural n is regarded as defined for each nN (inE1) if

(i) it is defined for n=1 and

(ii) some rule is given that expresses C(n+1) in terms of C(1),,C(n).

(Note 1 applies here, too.)

C(n) itself need not be a number; it may be of quite general nature.

We shall adopt this principle as a kind of logical axiom, without proof (though it can be proved in a similar manner as Theorems 1 and 2). The underlying intuitive idea is a "step-by-step" process - first, we define C(1); then, as C(1) is known, we may use it to define C(2); next, once both are known, we may use them to define C(3); and so on, ad infinitum. Definitions based on that principle are called inductive or recursive. The following examples are important.

Example 2.2.1 (continued)

(f) For any element x of a field, we define its nth power xn and its n-multiple nx by

(i) x1=1x=x
(ii) xn+1=xnx (respectively, (n+1)x=nx+x).

We may think of it as a step-by-step definition:

x1=x,x2=x1x,x3=x2x, etc.

(g) For each natural number n, we define its factorial n! by

1!=1,(n+1)!=n!(n+1);

e.g. ,2!=1!(2)=2,3!=2!(3)=6, etc. We also define 0!=1.

(h) The sum and product of n field elements x1,x2,,xn, denoted by

nk=1xk and nk=1xk

or

x1+x2++xn and x1x2xn, respectively

are defined recursively.

Sums are defined by

(i)1k=1xk=x1(ii)n+1k=1xk=(nk=1xk)+xn+1,n=1,2,

Thus

x1+x2+x3=(x1+x2)+x3

x1+x2+x3+x4=(x1+x2+x3)+x4, etc.

Products are defined by

(i)1k=1xk=x1(ii)n+1k=1xk=(nk=1xk)xn+1

(i) Given any objects x1,x2,,xn,, the ordered n-tuple

(x1,x2,,xn)

is defined inductively by

(i) (x1)=x1 (i.e., the ordered "one-tuple" (x1) is x1 itself ) and

(ii) (x1,x2,,xn+1)=((x1,,xn),xn+1), i.e., the ordered (n+1) tuple is a pair (y,xn+1) in which the first term y is itself an ordered n -tuple, (x1,,xn); for example,

(x1,x2,x3)=((x1,x2),x3), etc.


This page titled 2.2: Natural Numbers. Induction is shared under a CC BY 3.0 license and was authored, remixed, and/or curated by Elias Zakon (The Trilla Group (support by Saylor Foundation)) via source content that was edited to the style and standards of the LibreTexts platform.

Support Center

How can we help?